March 12, 2006

  • A Circle of Quiet

    From the Harvard Math Table page:

    “No Math table this week.
    We will reconvene next week on March 14 for
    a special Pi Day talk by Paul Bamberg.”

    The image “http://www.log24.com/log/pix06/060312-PaulBamberg21.jpg” cannot be displayed, because it contains errors.

    Paul Bamberg

    Transcript of the movie “Proof”–

    Some friends of mine are in this band.
    They’re playing in a bar on Diversey,
    way down the bill, around…

    I said I’d be there.

    Great.
    They’re all in the math department.
    They’re good.
    They have this song called “i.”
    You’d like it. Lowercase i.
    They just stand there.
    They don’t play anything for three minutes.

    Imaginary number?

    It’s a math joke.
    You see why they’re way down the bill.

    From the April 2006 Notices of the American Mathematical Society, a
    footnote in a review by Juliette Kennedy (pdf) of Rebecca Goldstein’s Incompleteness:

    4 There is a growing literature in the area of postmodern commentaries of [sic]
    Gödel’s theorems. For example, Régis Debray has used Gödel’s theorems
    to demonstrate the logical inconsistency of self-government. For a
    critical view of this and related developments, see Bricmont and
    Sokal’s Fashionable Nonsense [13]. For a more positive view see Michael
    Harris’s review of the latter, “I know what you mean!” [9]….

    [9] MICHAEL HARRIS, “I know what you mean!,” http://www.math.jussieu.fr/~harris/Iknow.pdf.
    [13] ALAN SOKAL and JEAN BRICMONT, Fashionable Nonsense, Picador, 1999.

    Following the trail marked by Ms. Kennedy, we find the following in Harris’s paper:

    “Their [Sokal's and Bricmont's] philosophy of mathematics, for instance,
    is summarized in the sentence ‘A mathematical constant like The image “http://www.log24.com/log/pix06/060312-Char-pi.jpg” cannot be displayed, because it contains errors. doesn’t
    change, even if the idea one has about it may change.’ ( p. 263). This
    claim, referring to a ‘crescendo of absurdity’ in Sokal’s original hoax
    in Social Text, is criticized by anthropologist Joan Fujimura, in an
    article translated for IS*. Most of Fujimura’s article consists of an
    astonishingly bland account of the history of non-euclidean geometry,
    in which she points out that the ratio of the circumference to the
    diameter depends on the metric. Sokal and Bricmont know this, and
    Fujimura’s remarks are about as helpful as FN’s** referral of Quine’s
    readers to Hume (p. 70). Anyway, Sokal explicitly referred to “Euclid’s
    pi”, presumably to avoid trivial objections like Fujimura’s — wasted
    effort on both sides.32 If one insists on making trivial objections,
    one might recall that the theorem
    that p is transcendental can be stated as follows: the homomorphism
    Q[X] –> R taking X to The image “http://www.log24.com/log/pix06/060312-Char-pi.jpg” cannot be displayed, because it contains errors. is injective.  In other words, The image “http://www.log24.com/log/pix06/060312-Char-pi.jpg” cannot be displayed, because it contains errors. can
    be identified algebraically with X, the variable par excellence.33

    The image “http://www.log24.com/log/pix06/060312-X.jpg” cannot be displayed, because it contains errors.

    More interestingly, one can ask what kind of object The image “http://www.log24.com/log/pix06/060312-Char-pi.jpg” cannot be displayed, because it contains errors. was before the formal definition
    of real numbers. To assume the real numbers were there all along,
    waiting to be defined, is to adhere to a form of Platonism.34  Dedekind wouldn’t have agreed.35  In a debate marked by the accusation that
    postmodern writers deny the reality of the external world, it is a
    peculiar move, to say the least, to make mathematical Platonism a
    litmus test for rationality.36 Not that it makes any more sense simply
    to declare Platonism out of bounds, like Lévy-Leblond, who calls
    Stephen Weinberg’s gloss on Sokal’s comment ‘une absurdité, tant il est
    clair que la signification d’un concept quelconque est évidemment
    affectée par sa mise en oeuvre dans un contexte nouveau!’37 Now I find
    it hard to defend Platonism with a straight face, and I prefer to
    regard the formula

    The image “http://www.log24.com/log/pix06/060312-pi.jpg” cannot be displayed, because it contains errors.

    as a creation rather than a discovery. But Platonism does correspond to
    the familiar experience that there is something about mathematics, and
    not just about other mathematicians, that precisely doesn’t let us get
    away with saying ‘évidemment’!38

    32 There are many circles in Euclid, but no pi, so I can’t think of any
    other reason for Sokal to have written ‘Euclid’s pi,’ unless this
    anachronism was an intentional part of the hoax.  Sokal’s full
    quotation was ‘the The image “http://www.log24.com/log/pix06/060312-Char-pi.jpg” cannot be displayed, because it contains errors.
    of Euclid and the G of Newton, formerly thought to be constant and
    universal, are now perceived in their ineluctable historicity.’ 
    But there is no need to invoke non-Euclidean geometry to perceive the
    historicity of the circle, or of pi: see Catherine Goldstein’s ‘L’un
    est l’autre: pour une histoire du cercle,’ in M. Serres, Elements d’histoire des sciences, Bordas, 1989, pp. 129-149.
    33 This is not mere sophistry: the construction of models over number
    fields actually uses arguments of this kind. A careless construction of
    the equations defining modular curves may make it appear that pi is
    included in their field of scalars.
    34 Unless you claim, like the present French Minister of Education [at
    the time of writing, i.e. 1999], that real numbers exist in nature,
    while imaginary numbers were invented by mathematicians. Thus The image “http://www.log24.com/log/pix06/060312-Char-pi.jpg” cannot be displayed, because it contains errors.
    would be a physical constant, like the mass of the electron, that can
    be determined experimentally with increasing accuracy, say by measuring
    physical circles with ever more sensitive rulers. This sort of position
    has not been welcomed by most French mathematicians.
    35 Cf. M. Kline, Mathematics The Loss of Certainty, p. 324.
    36 Compare Morris Hirsch’s remarks in BAMS April 94.
    37 IS*, p. 38, footnote 26. Weinberg’s remarks are
    contained in his article “Sokal’s Hoax,” in the New York Review of
    Books
    , August 8, 1996.
    38 Metaphors from virtual reality may help here.”

    * Earlier defined by Harris as “Impostures Scientifiques
    (IS), a collection of articles compiled or commissioned by Baudouin
    Jurdant and published simultaneously as an issue of the journal Alliage and as a book by La Découverte press.”
    ** Earlier defined by Harris as “Fashionable Nonsense (FN), the North American translation of Impostures Intellectuelles.”

    What is the moral of all this French noise?

    Perhaps that, in spite of the contemptible nonsense at last summer’s
    Mykonos conference on mathematics and narrative, stories do have an important role to play in mathematics — specifically, in the history of mathematics.

    Despite his disdain for Platonism, exemplified in his remarks on
    the noteworthy connection of pi with the zeta function in the formula
    given
    above, Harris has performed a valuable service to mathematics by
    pointing out the excellent historical work of Catherine Goldstein.   Ms.
    Goldstein has demonstrated that even a French nominalist can be a
    first-rate scholar.  Her essay on circles that Harris cites in a
    French version is also available in English, and will repay the study of
    those who, like Barry Mazur and other Harvard savants, are much too
    careless with the facts of history.  They should consult her
    “Stories of the Circle,” pp. 160-190 in A History of Scientific Thought, edited by Michel Serres, Blackwell Publishers (December 1995).

    For the historically-challenged mathematicians of Harvard, this
    essay would provide a valuable supplement to the upcoming “Pi Day” talk
    by Bamberg.

    For those who insist on limiting their attention to mathematics
    proper, and ignoring its history, a suitable Pi Day observance might include
    becoming familiar with various proofs of the formula, pictured
    above, that connects pi with the zeta function of 2.  For a survey,
    see Robin Chapman, Evaluating Zeta(2)
    (pdf).  Zeta functions in a much wider context will be discussed at next
    May’s politically correct “Women in Mathematics” program at Princeton, “Zeta Functions All the Way” (pdf).

Post a Comment

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *